Reading guide for Tues. 3/13 and Thurs. 3/15: Wittgenstein, selections from the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (handout and on line as pdf for viewing, and pdf for printing)
 

Wittgenstein’s Tractatus is made up of short sections that I will refer to as “remarks.” The key remarks for our purposes are numbered n, n.m, or n.0m. It has been suggested, for the remarks with such numbers, that n.1, n.2, etc. lead up to n+1 while n.01, n.02, etc. fall under n as further elaborations. It is okay to limit your reading to the remarks with these numbers but a few other remarks are included in the handout to provide some context and enable you to pursue ideas a little further if you are interested. Some of these further remarks also provide especially good examples of some of the ideas in the work, and I’ll refer you to those below. If you’d like even more context, you can find the full text in html format on the course Blackboard site; that form of the text indicates the remarks included on the handout, so you can see where they fall in the text as a whole.

The text can be divided roughly into the remarks before 4.1 and those from 4.1 on, and it’s natural to divide up our discussion in the same way, so read up to 4.1 for Tuesday.

• For our purposes, the key idea in first group is what is known as the “picture theory of meaning” (see, for example, 2.15). It is an alternative to an account of meaning offered by Russell. Russell thought propositions we can understand must be analyzable into “constituents” with which we are acquainted. Wittgenstein’s “objects” play a role analogous to Russell’s “constituents” with the important difference that an “object” in this sense brings with it all the possibilities of combining it with other objects to form a state of affairs. (Russell said, on the contrary, that we can be acquainted with a constituent without knowing anything about its relations.) The range of possible combinations of objects is one of the things Wittgenstein has in mind when he speaks of “logical space.”

• From 4.1 on, Wittgenstein can be understood to develop an alternative to an account of a priori knowledge offered by Russell. According to Russell, a priori knowledge was substantive knowledge of facts about universals (i.e., properties and relations). Remarks 4.46, 6.1, and 6.3 present the basic statement of Wittgenstein’s view, but his characterization of Newtonian mechanics as a conventional framework for describing nature (6.341 and 6.35) provides a more concrete way into the idea. Another way Wittgenstein uses to make his point that a priori truths have no content is the idea that they say nothing although they may show the structure of a language (see, for example, 6.12 and 6.13). Finally, notice the conception of philosophy sketched in the last few remarks and think how it is related to this conception of the a priori.

A guide to Wittgenstein’s notation in the Tractatus

• First his notation for logical operations:

• negation (‘not’) is expressed by the tilde (~)

• conjunction (‘and’) is expressed by a period

• disjunction (‘or’) is expressed by the letter ‘v’

• the conditional (‘if ... then’) is expressed by the right pointing horseshoe (⊃)

• the existential quantifier (‘some’ or ‘there exists’) is expressed by an inverted E (∃)

• The period is also used as symbolic punctuation whose function is roughly to mark the beginning of the parenthesized group (so the first period in 5.47 it indicates that the existential quantifier is applied to the full conjunction ‘fx.x=a’ rather than ‘fx’ alone).

• A right single quote is used to mark the application of an operation. (Wittgenstein distinguishes operations from functions: in this usage of these terms, addition and multiplication are operations but physical quantities varying with time or position are examples of functions.)

• Notation of the form ‘[a, x, O’x]’ indicates the collection of things that may be formed by beginning with a and repeatedly applying the operation O—i.e., moving from x to O’x. Thus ‘[0, x, x+1]’ indicates the accumulated results of beginning with 0 and repeatedly adding 1.

• Wittgenstein uses a bar over a variable to indicate the set of all possible values for that variable. This notation is analogous to a common notation for vectors except that it stands for a set rather than an ordered series of components.

• The summations in 4.27 and 4.42 use notation for the number of sets of a given size that can be drawn from a set of a given size (the number of “combinations of x things taken y at a time”) to write an expression for the number of ways of dividing a set into two parts. In 4.27 this gives the number of ways a collection of n states of affairs can be divided into those which exist and those which do not exist (or, equivalently, the number of “truth-possibilities” for n elementary propositions); and in 4.42, it gives the number of patterns of agreement and disagreement between a given proposition and the truth-possibilities of a group of n elementary propositions. (Simpler expressions can be given, 2n—i.e., 2 to the nth power—for the former and 2(2n) for the latter. For example, 23 (= 8) and 28 (= 256), respectively, for 3 elementary propositions.)