Phi 346 Sp12

Reading guide for Fri. 2/17: Quine, “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” §§V-VI, The Philosophical Review, vol. 60 (1951) (on JSTOR at 2181906, pp. 34-43)
 

The heart of Quine’s argument against the analytic/synthetic distinction lies in an attack on the verification theory of meaning that occupies the bulk of §V.

On p. 35, he presents the theory as he sees it and shows how, if sustainable, it would support the analytic/synthetic distinction.

Quine’s main target is a strong form of the verification theory which he calls “radical reductionism.” He describes and attacks this on pp. 36. Quine’s references to Carnap’s Aufbau (his Der logische Aufbau der Welt, or Logical Construction of the World) are rather sketchy, but they are important. Notice especially the reference to maximizing or minimizing “certain over-all features,” or achieving “the laziest world compatible with our experience” (both on p. 37).

Someone holding the verification theory need not be committed to radical reductionism and Quine indicates a less ambitious alternative beginning on p. 38. His argument against this “attenuated form” follows the same lines as his argument against the stronger version though it is necessarily less conclusive. He states it in the paragraph on the middle of p. 38.

Quine later added a footnote to this paragraph in which he referred to the physicist, philosopher, and historian of science Pierre Duhem (1861-1916), citing an argument of Duhem’s against the idea that experimental evidence could ever force anyone to reject a hypothesis. The reason Duhem denied this possibility was that further auxiliary assumptions are always required to tie a hypothesis to experimental tests—if only to predict the operation of experimental apparatus. And this means that, if the predicted result of an experiment fails, the hypothesis being tested can be retained if blame is cast on one of these other assumptions. Notice that this would mean that a hypothesis could not be tested by itself but only as a part of a “corporate body” including the further assumptions. In “Two Dogmas,” Quine strengthens Duhem’s claim, suggesting that Duhem’s point applies to all empirical statements and that no boundary can be drawn around the corporate body of assumptions relevant to any one of these statements.

Later on p. 38, Quine turns his arguments against the verification theory into an argument against the analytic/synthetic distinction. His argument goes roughly as follows. Anyone who maintains the analytic/synthetic distinction is committed to a distinction between factual and linguistic components of the truth of any statement—i.e., between the facts that make it true and the meaning that ties its truth to these facts. An empiricist will be committed also to the verification theory as an account of any meaning component of truth. But verificationism fails to assign meaning to individual statements. Thus, according to Quine, no empiricist can accept the analytic/synthetic distinction.

Quine’s concluding comment in this section—that the smallest meaningful unit is “the whole of science” (p. 39)—can be seen as his topic in the final section of the paper.

Quine’s alternative to the two “dogmas” that he has criticized centers on two ideas, each taking up about half of §VI.

The first is the comparison of our beliefs to a field of force underdetermined by its boundary conditions in experience (pp. 39f). A standard concrete image for a field with boundary conditions is a flexible sheet (for a drumhead perhaps) being pulled at its edges. The field would be undetermined if the forces at its edges did not uniquely determine the positions of interior points—for an extreme case of this, imagine the sheet is made of bubble gum.

Quine’s second way of filling out his alternative to the dogmas (pp. 41ff) lies in his idea of “posits” and his claim that various such posits—e.g., “brick houses on Elm Street” (pp. 40, 43)—differ from centaurs or Homer’s gods “only in degree and not in kind” (p. 41).

Quine points to some of the consequences of these ways of thinking about science and our knowledge generally, but you should try to explore them further still. Do they seem to provide an acceptable alternative to one based on a distinction between linguistic understanding and factual reality?